dc.contributor | Cussins, Adrian | |
dc.contributor | Filosofía y Cognición | |
dc.creator | Pinzón Duarte, John Anderson | |
dc.date.accessioned | 2020-03-06T14:15:07Z | |
dc.date.available | 2020-03-06T14:15:07Z | |
dc.date.created | 2020-03-06T14:15:07Z | |
dc.date.issued | 2019-12-11 | |
dc.identifier | Pinzón Duarte, John Anderson "Atención conjunta mediada" Disertación doctoral, Universidad Nacioanl de Colombia, 2019 | |
dc.identifier | https://repositorio.unal.edu.co/handle/unal/75919 | |
dc.description.abstract | En esta disertación sugiero una respuesta a la pregunta ‘¿Qué es la atención conjunta?’. La respuesta re-quiere de la articulación de dos elementos: (i) una caracterización de qué tipo de fenómeno estamos ha-blando y (ii) una explicación adecuada de dicho fenómeno. Respecto a (i) argumento que una correcta caracterización de este fenómeno implica afirmar que la atención conjunta es un episodio de interacción social en el que se resuelve tareas cooperativamente mediante la comunicación, cuya cooperación es depen-diente de lo que se conoce como apertura perceptual. A propósito de (ii) recojo los argumentos que sostienen la idea según la cual un episodio de atención conjunta se explica a partir de un entendimien-to/conocimiento fundamentalmente perceptual, compartido y no-proposicional. Una manera adecuada de articular (i) y (ii) consiste en ofrecer una especificación de dicho entendimiento/conocimiento y una des-cripción de cómo éste puede dar cuenta de dos rasgos esenciales de la atención conjunta: la cooperación y la apertura perceptual. De acuerdo con (ii), sólo una teoría de la percepción puede ofrecer los recursos teórico-conceptuales para esta tarea.
Únicamente dos aproximaciones teóricas acerca de la percepción han ofrecido una respuesta a la pregunta por la atención conjunta: el ‘enfoque relacional de la experiencia’ y el ‘enactivismo autopoietico’. Con el objetivo de formular mi propia respuesta, rechazaré el ‘enfoque relacional’ y modificaré el ‘enactivismo autopoietico’. En contra del ‘enfoque relacional de la experiencia’ argumentaré que los recursos teórico-conceptuales de este enfoque son inadecuados para dar cuenta de la atención conjunta en cuanto que son insuficientes para establecer una diferencia metafísica entre episodios de atención conjunta y episodios de atención individual paralela. Un camino para superar esta dificultad consiste en afirmar —junto con el ‘enactivismo autopoietico’— que la interacción social es parte constitutiva de la percepción que soporta a los episodios de atención conjunta pero no de los episodios de atención individual paralela. Aunque la idea me parece esencialmente correcta, en contra del ‘enactivismo autopoietico’ argüiré que sus recursos teóri-co-conceptuales son inadecuados porque son insuficientes para dar cuenta de la cooperación y la apertura perceptual involucrada en la atención conjunta. El ‘enactivismo autopoietico’ implica que la interacción social que constituye la percepción es un fenómeno autónomo. Sin embargo, argumentaré que la coopera-ción y la apertura perceptual requieren un grado de heteronomía en su interacción social. Mi sugerencia será afirmar que una explicación adecuada de la atención conjunta implica que la percepción está constituida por un tipo de interacción social parcialmente autónomo y parcialmente heterónomo: el rasgo autónomo da cuenta del carácter social de la atención conjunta y el rasgo heterónomo da cuenta de su cooperación y apertura perceptual.
Finalmente, diré que la forma que toma esta sugerencia explicativa consiste en la idea según la cual la per-cepción que ayuda a explicar la atención conjunta tiene la estructura de un turno conversacional: esto es, es un episodio cooperativo estructurado en términos de toma-de-turnos donde cada sujeto individual contribuye a sedimentar (o ‘hacer público’) cuáles aspectos del ambiente hacen parte de una tarea. La estructura con-versacional de la percepción implica que (a) la percepción está orientada por la sensibilidad a propiedades disposicionales del ambiente material: affordances-afectivos que sirven como medio para resolver tareas, e implica (b) un entendimiento/conocimiento perceptual respecto de los aspectos ambientales sedimentados conversacionalmente. Si (a) y (b) se cumplen, entonces se obtiene un entendimiento/conocimiento adecua-do para dar cuenta de la cooperación y la apertura perceptual de la atención conjunta.
Cualquier episodio de atención conjunta que dependa de la estructura conversacional de la percepción será un episodio de atención conjunta mediada. Y, según yo argumento, debido a que una explicación adecuada de la atención conjunta implica las afirmaciones (a) y (b), entonces la atención conjunta correctamente expli-cada es atención conjunta mediada. Así, mi sugerencia explicativa será que la atención conjunta correcta-mente explicada es ‘atención conjunta mediada’. | |
dc.description.abstract | In this dissertation, I propose an answer to the question "What is joint attention?" based on the articulation of: (i) a characterization of what kind of phenomenon we are talking about and (ii) an adequate explanation of such phenomenon. Regarding (i), I claim that an accurate characterization of this phenomenon implies that joint attention is a social interaction bout in which, at least, two sub-jects are cooperatively solving a task through communication, and whose cooperation depends on what is called perceptual openness. With respect to (ii), I rely on the arguments that support the idea ac-cording to which a joint attention bout is explained by fundamentally perceptual, shared and non-propositional understanding/knowledge. I argue that a correct way of articulating (i) and (ii) is to offer both, a specification of such understanding/knowledge and a description of how such under-standing/knowledge can account for two essential features of joint attention: cooperation and per-ceptual openness. According to (ii), only a theory of perception can offer the theoretical-conceptual frame needed for this task.
Only two theoretical approaches to perception have attempted to offer an answer to the question about joint attention: the ‘relational view of experience’ and ‘autopoietic enactivism’. In order to frame my own answer, I reject the ‘relational view’ and modify the ‘autopoietic enactivism’. Against the ‘relational view of experience’, I argue that its theoretical-conceptual resources are inadequate to account for joint attention in so far they fail to establish a metaphysical distinction between joint attentional and parallel individual attentional bouts. One way to overcome this difficulty is to hold —along with ‘autopoietic enactivism’—that social interaction is a constitutive part of the perception that supports joint attentional bouts but not the individual parallel ones. Although this idea seems to me exactly correct, I do not side with ‘autopoietic enactivism’, for its theoretical-conceptual resources are insufficient to account for the cooperation and perceptual openness involved in joint attention. ‘Au-topoietic enactivism’ entails that the social interaction that constitutes perception is an autonomous phenomenon. But, I argue, cooperation and perceptual openness requires a degree of heteronomy in their social interaction. My suggestion is that to state that a correct explanation of joint attention en-tails that a form of perception that is constituted by a type of partly autonomous, partly heterono-mous social interaction: the autonomous side of the social interaction accounts for its social charac-ter and the heteronomous side accounts for its cooperation and perceptual openness.
Finally, I claim that the general form of my suggestion consists in the idea that perception that sup-ports joint attention has a “conversational-turn” structure: that is, a cooperative turn-taking structured bout where each individual contributes to grounding or ‘make public’ certain aspects of the environ-ment as part of a task. The conversational structure of perception implies two things: (a) perception is oriented by the sensitivity to dispositional properties of the material environment: an affective-affordances structure that behave as means to solve tasks, and (b) a perceptual understand-ing/knowledge concerning conversationally grounded environmental aspects. If (a) and (b) are both settled, then an adequate understanding/knowledge is obtained which sufficiently accounts for the cooperation and perceptual openness of joint attention.
I hold that any joint attentional bout that depends on the conversational structure of perception will be an episode of joint mediated attention. And because an adequate explanation of joint attention in-volves statements (a) and (b), then a correct version of joint attention is joint mediated attention. So, my proposal in this dissertation will be: Joint attention adequately explained is ‘joint mediated attention’. | |
dc.language | spa | |
dc.publisher | Departamento de Filosofía | |
dc.publisher | Universidad Nacional de Colombia - Sede Bogotá | |
dc.relation | Alfieri, J. 2010 “Teaching Joint Attention Skills in Young Learners with ASD”, Informe de Gestión. Recuperado de https://s3-us-west-2.amazonaws.com/palms-awss3-repository/Shared_Con tent/BAS/ASERT/ASERT+1332/ASERT+1332+Teaching+Joint+Atten ion+Skills+in+Young+Learners+wtih+ASD.pdf | |
dc.relation | Apperly, I, & Butterfill, S. 2009 “Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states?” Psychol. Rev. 116: 953–70 | |
dc.relation | Auvray, M., Lenay, C., Stewart, J., 2008 “Perceptual interactions in a minimalist virtual environment”, New Ideas in Psychology, doi:10.1016/j.newideapsych.2007.12.002 | |
dc.relation | Bakhurst, D. 2016 “Activity and the Search for True Materialism”, En: Maidansky, Andrey & Vesa Oittinen (eds.), The Practical Essence of Man: The ‘Activity approach’ in the Late Soviet, Historical materialism book se-ries, Brill Press, Leiden, The Netherlands | |
dc.relation | Baldwin, D. A. 1995 “Understanding the Link between Joint Attention and Language” En: Moore, Ch., & Dunham, Ph. (eds) Joint Attention: Its origins and Role in Development, Psychology Press (Taylor and Francis Group), NewYork/Sussex. (1995/2014) | |
dc.relation | Baron-Cohen, S., 1995 “The Eye Direction Detector (EDD) and the Shared Attention Mechanism (SAM): Two Cases for Evolutionary Psychology”, En: Moore, Ch., & Dunham, Ph. (eds) Joint Attention: Its origins and Role in Development, Psychology Press (Taylor and Francis Group), NewYork/Sussex. (1995/2014) | |
dc.relation | Bates, E., Camaioni, L., Volterra, V. 1975 “The Acquisition of Performatives prior to Speech”, Merrill-Palmer Quarterly of Behavior and Devel-opment, Vol. 21, No. 3 (JULY 1975), pp. 205-226 | |
dc.relation | Bigelow, A.E., 2003 “The development of joint attention in blind infants”, Development and Psychopathology, 15 (2003), 259– 275 | |
dc.relation | Blomberg, O., 2016 “Common Knowledge and Reductionism about Shared Agency” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 94:2, 315-326 | |
dc.relation | Botero, J.J. 1988 “Husserl y la Posibilidad”, Ideas y Valores, 78, 51-63. | |
dc.relation | Bratman, M. 2014 Shared Agency. A planning Theory of Acting Together. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK. | |
dc.relation | Brinck, I. 2004a “Joint Attention, Triangulation and Radical Interpretation: A Problem and its Solution” Dialectica Vol. 58, No. 2 (2004), pp. 179-205 | |
dc.relation | Brinck, I. 2004b “The Pragmatics of Imperative and Declarative Pointing” Cognitive Science Quarterly (2004) 3(4), 429-446 | |
dc.relation | Bruner, J.S. 1995 “From Joint Attention to Meeting of Minds: an Introduction”. En: Moore, Ch., & Dunham, Ph. (eds) Joint Attention: Its origins and Role in Development, Psychology Press (Taylor and Francis Group), NewYork/Sussex. (1995/2014) | |
dc.relation | Butterworth, G. 1995 “Origins of Mind in Perception and Action” En: Moore, Ch., & Dunham, Ph. (eds) Joint Attention: Its origins and Role in Development, Psychology Press (Taylor and Francis Group), NewYork/Sussex. (1995/2014) | |
dc.relation | Butterworth, G. “Origins of Joint Visual Attention in Infancy” Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Develop-ment, Vol. 63, No. 4, pp. i+iii+v-vi+1-174. | |
dc.relation | Call, J., Hare, B., & Tomasello, M. 1998 “Chimpanzee gaze following in an object-choice task” Animal Cognition (1998) 1:89–99 | |
dc.relation | Call, J. & Tomasello, M. 2005 “What Chimpanzees Know about Seeing, revisited: An Explanation of the Third Kind”, En: Eilan, N. Horel, Ch., McCormack, T, and Roessler, J. Joint Attention Communication and Other Minds, Issues in Philosophy and Psychology Oxford UP | |
dc.relation | Campbell, J. 2002 Reference and Consciousness, Oxford U.P. | |
dc.relation | Campbell, J. 2005 “Joint Attention and Common Knowledge”, En: Eilan, N. Horel, Ch., McCormack, T, and Roess-ler, J. Joint Attention Communication and Other Minds, Issues in Philosophy and Psychology Oxford UP | |
dc.relation | Campbell, J. 2009 “Consciousness and Reference”, En: Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter (eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind (Enero 2009) DOI: 10.1093/ox fordhb/9780199262618.003.0038 | |
dc.relation | Campbell, J. 2010 “Joint Attention and the First Person”, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 43, 123-136. doi:10.1017/S1358246100004331 (publicado 1998/ publicado online 2010) | |
dc.relation | Campbell, J. 2011 “An object-dependent view of joint attention”, En: Seemann Axel. Joint Attention: New Developments in Psychology, Philosophy of mind and Social Neuroscience. MIT Cambridge. Ma. | |
dc.relation | Cappuccio, M. 2013a Pointing: Where Embodied Cognition meets Symbolic Mind. Humana Mente, 24. (ed.) Journal of Phil-osophical Studies (Recuperado Junio 2018 de http://www.humanamente.eu/index.php/HM/issue/view/30) | |
dc.relation | Cappuccio, M. 2013b “Pointing: A Gesture That Makes Us Special?”, En: Massimiliano Cappuccio (ed). Pointing: Where Embodied Cognition meets Symbolic Mind. Humana Mente, 24. Journal of Philosophical Studies, pág XI-XL | |
dc.relation | Carpenter, M., Nagell, K. & Tomasello, M., 1998 “Social Cognition, Joint Attention, and Communicative Competence from 9 to 15 Months of Age”, Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, Vol. 63, No. 4, pp. 1-174. | |
dc.relation | Carpenter, M. & Liebal, K 2011 “Joint Attention, Communication and Knowing Together in Infancy” En: Seemann, A. (ed.), Joint Attention: New Developments in Psychology Philosophy of Mind, and Social Neuroscience, MIT Press 2011. | |
dc.relation | Charles, D. 2001 “Wittgenstein’s Builders and Aristotle’s Craftsmen”, in David Charles and William Child (eds) Wittgensteinian Themes: Essays in Honor of David Pears. New York: Oxford | |
dc.relation | Clark, A. 2005 “World, Niche and Super Niche: How Language Makes Mind Matters More” Theoria 54: 255-268 | |
dc.relation | Clark, A. 2006 “Vision as dance? Three challenges for sensorimotor contingency theory” Psyche, 12 (2006), pp. 1-10 | |
dc.relation | Clark, H. 2003 “Pointing and Placing”, en Sotaro Kita (ed.) Pointing: Where Language, Culture and Cognition Meet. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Publishers, New York. | |
dc.relation | Clark, H., & Krych, M., 2004 “Speaking while monitoring addressees for understanding.” Journal of Memory and Language, no. 50 (2004): 62-81. | |
dc.relation | Cussins, A 1992 “Content, Embodiment and Objectivity: The Theory of Cognitive Trails” Mind, Vol. 101. 404 (October 1992) | |
dc.relation | Davies, M. 1994 “The Mental Simulation Debate” Philosophical Issues, Vol. 5, Truth and Rationality (1994), pp. 189-218 | |
dc.relation | Davidson, D. 1973 “Radical Interpretation”, Dialectica, 27, pp. 313-328 | |
dc.relation | Davidson, D. 1989 “The Conditions of Thought” Le Cahier (Collège international de philosophie), No. 7 (avril 1989), pp. 165-171. | |
dc.relation | Davidson, D. 1997 “The Emergency of Thought”, En Subjective, Intersubjective and Objective, Oxford U.P. | |
dc.relation | De Jaegher, H., 2006 Social Interaction Rhythm and Participatory Sense-Making: An Embodied, Interactional Approach to Social Understanding, with Some Implications for Autism. Tesis Doctoral, Sussex: University of Sussex, 2006. | |
dc.relation | De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E., 2007 “Participatory sense-making: An enactive approach to social cognition” Phenom Cogn Sci 6:485–507 doi 10.1007/s11097-007-9076-9 | |
dc.relation | De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E., & Gallagher, S. 2010 “Can social interaction constitute social cognition?” Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14, 441–447. | |
dc.relation | Di Paolo, E. & De Jaegher, H. 2017 “Neither Individualistic nor Interactionist”, En: Chirstoph Durt, Thomas Fuchs, Christian Tewes (eds.) Embodiment, Enaction, and Culture: investigating the constitution of the shared world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press | |
dc.relation | Di Paolo, E., Cuffari, E. C., & De Jaegher, H. 2018 Linguistic Bodies. The Continuity between life and language, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press | |
dc.relation | Dunham, Ph., & Dunham, F. 1995 “Optimal Social Structures and Adaptive Infant Development” En: Moore, Ch., & Dunham, Ph. (eds) Joint Attention: Its origins and Role in Development, Psychology Press (Taylor and Francis Group), New York/Sussex. (1995/2014) | |
dc.relation | Egbert, M., Golato, A., & Robinson, J. 2009 “Repairing Reference” En: Jack Sidnell (ed.) Conversation Analysis: Comparative Perspectives. Studies in Interactional Sociolinguistics. 27. Cambridge U. Press. | |
dc.relation | Eilan, N. 2005 “Joint Attention, Communication and Mind”, En: Eilan, N. Horel, Ch., McCormack, T, and Roessler, J. Joint Attention, Communication and Other Minds, Issues in Philosophy and Psychology Oxford UP | |
dc.relation | Eilan, N. 2007 “Consciousness, Self-consciousness and Communication”, En: Baldwin, Th. (ed) Reading Merleau-Ponty on Phenomenology of Perception” Routledge, London, pp. 118-138. | |
dc.relation | Eilan, N. 2014 “Joint Attention and the Second Person” (Draft, recuperado en febrero de 2018) https://warwick.ac.uk/fac/soc/philosophy/people/eilan/jasphum.pdf | |
dc.relation | Eilan, N. Horel, Ch., McCormack, T, and Roessler, J. 2005 Joint Attention Communication and Other Minds, Issues in Philosophy and Psychology Oxford UP | |
dc.relation | Evans, G. 1982 The Varieties of Reference Oxford UP. | |
dc.relation | Fiebich, A. & Gallagher, Sh. 2012 “Joint attention in joint action” Philosophical Psychology, 26:4, 571-587. | |
dc.relation | Fodor, J., 1975 The Language of Thought. MIT Press, Thomas Y. Crowell Company, Inc. Mass. US | |
dc.relation | Froese, T., and Di Paolo. E., 2011 “The Enactive Approach: Theoretical Sketches From Cell to Society” Pragmatics & Cognition 19:1 (2011), 1-36. | |
dc.relation | Fuchs, T., y De Jaegher, H. 2009 “Enactive intersubjectivity: Participatory sense-making and mutual incorporation” Phenom Cogn Sci 8:465–486 | |
dc.relation | Gallagher, S. 1986 “Body Image and Body Schema: a conceptual clarification” Journal of Mind and Behaviour 7 (4):541 554 | |
dc.relation | Gallagher, S. 2001 “The Practice of Mind: Theory, simulation or interaction?” Journal of Consciousness Studies 8/5–7 (2001): 83–108 | |
dc.relation | Gallagher, S. 2007 “Logical and Phenomenological Arguments against Simulation Theory”, En: Hutto, Daniel D. & Ratcliffe, Matthew (eds.). Folk Psychology Re- Assesed Dordrecth, Netherlands, pp. 63 – 78. | |
dc.relation | Gallagher, S. 2008 “Direct perception in the intersubjective context”, Consciousness and Cognition 17 (2008): 535 – 543. | |
dc.relation | Gallagher, S. 2010a “Joint attention, joint action, and participatory sense making” Alert: Revue de Phénoménologie (18): 111- 124. | |
dc.relation | Gallagher, S. 2010b “Movement and Emotion in Joint Attention”, En: Sabine Flach, Daniel Margulies & Jan Söffner (eds.) Habitus in Habitat I: Emotion and Motion. Peter Lang AG, International Academic Publishers, Berna. | |
dc.relation | Gallagher, S. 2011a “Strong Interaction and Self-Agency” Humana Mente 4 (15):55-76 | |
dc.relation | Gallagher, S. 2011b “Interactive Coordination in Joint Attention”, En: Seemann, A. (ed.), Joint Attention: New Developments in Psychology Philosophy of Mind, and Social Neuroscience, MIT Press 2011. | |
dc.relation | Gallagher, S., and D.D. Hutto. 2008 “Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice”, En: J. Zlatev, T.P. Racine, C. Sinha and E. Itkonen (eds.) The shared mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity, Págs. 17–38. Amsterdam: John Benjamins | |
dc.relation | Garavito, M. 2020 “Debates sobre atención conjunta en ciencias cognitivas y fenomenología” En: Rivera, Ángel., Espejo-Serna, Juan., y Castiblanco, Porfirio., (eds.) Imágenes de la mente, el lenguaje y el conocimiento, Universidad Nacional de Colombia Editorial. En prensa. | |
dc.relation | Gibson, J.J. 1979 The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Publishers, Hillsdale, New Jersey (edición 1986) | |
dc.relation | Gilbert, M. 1990 “Walking Together: A Paradigmatic Social Phenomenon” Midwest Studies In Philosophy 15: 1–14. | |
dc.relation | Gilbert, M. 2014 Joint Commitment. How We Make the Social World, Oxford U. Press. New York. | |
dc.relation | Gómez, J.C., 2005 “Joint Attention and the Notion of Subject: Insights from Apes, Normal Children and Children with Autism” En: Eilan, N. Horel, Ch., McCormack, T, and Roessler, J. Joint Attention, Communica-tion and Other Minds, Issues in Philosophy and Psychology Oxford UP | |
dc.relation | Grice, H. P. 1957 “Meaning.” Philosophical Review 66:377–388 | |
dc.relation | Heal, J. 2005 “Joint Attention and Understanding the Mind”, En: Eilan, N. Horel, Ch., McCormack, T, and Roess- ler, J. Joint Attention Communication and Other Minds, Issues in Philosophy and Psychology Oxford UP | |
dc.relation | Hobson, P 2005 “What puts the Jointness into Joint Attention?”, En: Eilan, N. Horel, Ch., McCormack, T, and Roess- ler, J. Joint Attention Communication and Other Minds, Issues in Philosophy and Psychology Oxford UP | |
dc.relation | Hobson, P. & Hobson, J. 2008 “Engaging, sharing, knowing: Some lessons from research in autism”, En: Zlatev, J. Racine, T., Shina, Ch., Itkonen, I. (eds.) The Shared Mind: Perspectives on Intersubjectivity. John Benjamins Publishing Com pany Amsterdam / Philadelphia | |
dc.relation | Hobson, P. & Hobson, J. 2011 “Joint Attention or Joint Engagement? Insights from Autism”, En: Seemann, A. (ed.), Joint Atten-tion: New Developments in Psychology Philosophy of Mind, and Social Neuroscience, MIT Press 2011. | |
dc.relation | Hutto, D., 2008 Folk psychological narratives: The sociocultural basis of understanding reasons MIT Press. | |
dc.relation | Hutto, D. 2011 “Elementary Mind Minding, Enactivist-Style”, En: Seemann, A. (ed.), Joint Attention: New Develop-ments in Psychology Philosophy of Mind, and Social Neuroscience, MIT Press 2011 | |
dc.relation | Ikegami, T, y Iizuka, H. 2007 “Turn-taking Interaction as a Cooperative and Co-creative Process” Infant Behavior & Development 30 (2007) 278–288 | |
dc.relation | Itakura, Sh. 2004 “Gaze‐following and joint visual attention in nonhuman animals” Japanese Psychological Research, 46(3), 216–26 | |
dc.relation | Kaminski, Juliane, Julia Riedel, Josep Call y Michaell Tomasello 2005 “Domestic goats, Capra hircus, follow gaze direction and use social cues in an object choice task” Animal Behaviour, 2005, 69, 11–18 | |
dc.relation | Kaptelinin, V., & Nardi, E. 2006 “Activity Theory in a Nutshell”, En: Bonnie Nardi, Victor Kaptelinin, and Kirsten Foot (eds.) Acting with Technology: Activity Theory and Interaction Design. MIT Press, Cambridge Mass. Páginas 29-72. | |
dc.relation | Kendon, A. 1990 Conducting Interaction. Patterns of Behavior in Focused Encounters (Studies in Interactional Sociolinguistics, 7), Cambridge UP. Cambridge. | |
dc.relation | Lawton K. & Kasari C. 2013 “Initiating/Responding to Joint Attention Skills (IJA/RJA)”. En: Volkmar F.R. (eds) Encyclopedia of Autism Spectrum Disorders. Springer, New York, NY | |
dc.relation | Leavens, D. 2004 “Manual deixis in apes and humans” Interaction Studies 5:3 (2004) 387–408. | |
dc.relation | Leavens, D. 2011 “Joint Attention: Twelve Myths”, En: Seemann Axel. Joint Attention: New Developments in Psychology, Philosophy of mind and Social Neuroscience. MIT Cambridge. Ma | |
dc.relation | Leavens, D., & Racine, T., 2009 “Joint Attention in Apes and Humans: Are Humans Unique?” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 16, No. 6–8, 2009, pp. 240–67 | |
dc.relation | Leavens, D., Hopkins, W., and Brad, K. 2008 “The heterochronic origins of explicit reference”, En: Jordan Zlatev, Tim Racine, Chris Shina, Esa Itkonen (eds.) The Shared Mind: Perspectives on Intersubjectivity, John Bemhamin Publishing Company, Amsterdam, Netherlands, pgs. 187-214 | |
dc.relation | León, F, & Zahavi, D. 2016 “Phenomenology of experiential sharing: The contribution of Schutz and Walther”. En A. Salice & H. B. Schmid (Eds.), The phenomenological approach to social reality: History, concepts, problems (pp. 219–234). Cham: Springer International Publishing. | |
dc.relation | Lewis, D. 1969 Convention, A philosophical Study, Blackwell Publishers, Oxford U.P. (edición 2002) | |
dc.relation | Liszkowski, U., M. Carpenter, A. Henning, T. Striano, and M. Tomasello. 2004 “Twelve-month-olds point to share attention and interest” Developmental Science 7:297–307 | |
dc.relation | Maidansky, A & Oittinen, V 2016 “Introduction” En: Maidansky, Andrey & Vesa Oittinen (eds.), The Practical Essence of Man: The ‘Ac tivity approach’ in the Late Soviet, Historical materialism book series, Brill Press, Leiden, The Netherlands. | |
dc.relation | Martin, M 1998 “Setting Things Before the Mind”, En: O'Hear, A, (ed.) Current Issues in Philosophy of Mind, 157-179. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge | |
dc.relation | McDowell, J. 1994 Mind and World, Harvard U.P., London. | |
dc.relation | McDowell, J. 1998 “Meaning, Communication and Knowledge”, En: McDowell, J. Meaning, Knowledge and Reality, Harvard U.P. Cambridge, Mass | |
dc.relation | McDowell, J. 2008 “Avoiding the Myth of the Given”. En: Lindgaard, J. (ed.) John McDowell: Experience, Norm and Nature. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford. | |
dc.relation | Milnor, J. 1985 “On the concept of attractor” Commun. Math. Phys. 99, 177–195 | |
dc.relation | Moll, H. y Meltzoff, A. 2011 “Joint Attention as the Fundamental Basis of Understanding Perspective” En: Seemann Axel. Joint Attention: New Developments in Psychology, Philosophy of mind and Social Neuroscience. MIT Cambridge. Ma | |
dc.relation | Moore, Ch., & Dunham, Ph. (eds) 1995 Joint Attention: Its origins and Role in Development, Psychology Press (Taylor and Francis Group), NewYork/Sussex. (1995/2014) | |
dc.relation | Mundy, P., & Newell, L., 2007 “Attention, Joint Attention, and Social Cognition” Currents Directions in Psychological Science, 2007 Oct 1; 16(5): 269–274. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8721.2007.00518.x | |
dc.relation | Murray, L. and C. Trevarthen 1985 “Emotional regulation of interactions between 2-month-olds and their mothers”, En: T.M. Field and N.A. Fox (eds.) Social Perception in Infants. Norwood, NJ, Ablex | |
dc.relation | Murray, L. and C. Trevarthen 1986 “The infant’s role in mother-infant communication." Journal of Child Language 13: 15-29. | |
dc.relation | Nadel Jacqueline, Isabelle Charcon, Claude Kervella, Daniel Marcelli, and Denis Réserbat-Plantey 1999 “Expectancies for Social Contingency in 2-months-old”, Developmental Science 2:2, pp. 164-173. | |
dc.relation | Noë, A. 2004 Action in Perception, MIT Press, London. | |
dc.relation | Noë, A. 2012 Varieties of Presence, Harvard U. Press. Cambridge Mass. | |
dc.relation | Núñez, M., 2015 “Joint attention in Deafblind Children: A Multisensory Path towards a shared sense of the world” Extended Report, Galsgow: Galsgow Calendonian University, 2015. | |
dc.relation | Olney, A., M. 2013 “Symbolic, Indexical, and Iconic Communication with Domestic Dogs” En: Cappucio, M. (ed) Pointing: Where Embodied Cognition meets Symbolic Mind. Humana Mente, 24. Journal of Philosophi-cal Studies. | |
dc.relation | Peacocke, Ch. 1992 A Study of Concepts, MIT Cambridge Mass. | |
dc.relation | Peacocke, Ch. 2005 “Joint Attention: Its Nature, Reflexivity, and Relation to Common Knowledge” En: Eilan, N. Horel, Ch., McCormack, T, and Roessler, J. Joint Attention Communication and Other Minds, Issues in Philosophy and Psychology Oxford UP. | |
dc.relation | Pinzón Duarte, J.A 2020 “Discutiendo sobre atención conjunta con una fenomenóloga”, En: Rivera, Ángel., Espejo-Serna, Juan., y Castiblanco, Porfirio., (eds.) Imágenes de la mente, el lenguaje y el conocimiento, Universidad Na-cional | |
dc.relation | Pinzón Duarte, J. A., 2018 “Así no se explica la atención conjunta”, Ideas y Valores 67 Suplemento No. 4: 15-39 (2018) | |
dc.relation | Racine, T., P. 2011 “Getting Beyond Rich and Lean Views of Joint Attention”, En: Seemann Axel. Joint Attention: New Developments in Psychology, Philosophy of mind and Social Neuroscience. MIT Cambridge. Ma | |
dc.relation | Racine, T. P., & Carpendale, J. I. M. 2007 “The role of the Shared Practice in Joint Attention” British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 25, 3-25 | |
dc.relation | Rechele B & Meltzoff, A. 2014 “Gaze Following: a mechanism for building social connections between infants and adults” En: M. Mikulincer & P.R. Shaver (Eds.), Nature and development of social connections: From brain to group. Wash ington DC: American Psychological Association. | |
dc.relation | Rechele B & Meltzoff, A. 2012 “Gaze Following: A Key to Understanding Self, Other, and Language Development” Draft, avail-able at http://portal.idc.ac.il/en/symposium/hspsp/2012/documents/cbrooks12.pdf | |
dc.relation | Reddy, V., 2005 “Before the ‘Third Element’: Understanding Attention to Self”, En: Eilan, N., Roessler J., Hoerl Ch., McCormack T. Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds. Oxford U.P. 2005 | |
dc.relation | Reddy, V. 2011 “A Gaze at Grips with me” En: Seemann Axel. Joint Attention: New Developments in Psychology, Philos-ophy of mind and Social Neuroscience. MIT Cambridge. Ma | |
dc.relation | Roessler, J. 2005 “Joint Attention and the Problem of Other minds”, En: Eilan, N. Horel, Ch., McCormack, T, and Roessler, J. Joint Attention Communication and Other Minds, Issues in Philosophy and Psychology Oxford UP. | |
dc.relation | Roessler, J. 2005 “Joint Attention and the Problem of Other minds”, En: Eilan, N. Horel, Ch., McCormack, T, and Roessler, J. Joint Attention Communication and Other Minds, Issues in Philosophy and Psychology Oxford UP. | |
dc.relation | Scaife, M. y Bruner, J. S., 1975 “The capacity for joint visual attention in the infant” Nature 253, 265–266 (24 January 1975) | |
dc.relation | Schiffer, S., 1972 Meaning, Oxford, Clarendon Press (edición 2002). | |
dc.relation | Searle, J. 1990 “Collective Intention and Action”, En: Philip R. Cohen, Jerry Morgan and Martha E. Pollack (Eds.) Intentions in Communcation, MIT Press Mass. pp. 401-415. | |
dc.relation | Seemann, A., 2011 “Joint Attention: Toward a Relational Account”, En: Seemann Axel. Joint Attention: New Develop-ments in Psychology, Philosophy of mind and Social Neuroscience. MIT Cambridge. Ma. | |
dc.relation | Seemann, A. 2011a (ed.) Joint Attention: New Developments in Psychology Philosophy of Mind, and Social Neuroscience, MIT Press. | |
dc.relation | Seemann, 2019 The Shared World: perceptual common knowledge, demonstrative communication, and social space, The MIT Press Cambridge, MA | |
dc.relation | Rietveld, E. & Kiverstein, E. 2014 “A Rich Landscape of Affordances” Ecological Psychology, 26, 325-352 | |
dc.relation | Shepherd, S 2010 “Following gaze: gaze-following behavior as a window into social cognition” Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience, 4 (5) 1-13. | |
dc.relation | Siposova, B. & Carpenter, M. 2019 “A new look at joint attention and common knowledge” Cognition 189 (2019) 260–274 | |
dc.relation | Soproni, K., Miklósi, A., Topál, J., & Csányi, V. 2002 “Dogs'(Canis familaris) responsiveness to human pointing gestures”. Journal of Comparative Psycholo-gy, 116(1). | |
dc.relation | Soteriou, M., 2016 Disyunctivism, (New Problems of Philosophy Series) Routledge, New York, USA. | |
dc.relation | Steiner, P. and Stewart, J. 2009. “From autonomy to heteronomy (and back): The enaction of social life”. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8(4): 527–550 | |
dc.relation | Strawson, P. F. 1959 Individuals. An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics. Routledge, Taylor and Francis Group. London. Ed. 2006 | |
dc.relation | Strawson, P. F. 1964 “Intention and Convention in Speech Acts”, The Philosophical Review, Vol. 73, No. 4. (Oct., 1964), pp. 439-460 | |
dc.relation | Sultanescu, O & Andrews, K. 2013 “Are Apes’ Responses to Pointing Gestures Intentional?” En: Cappucio, M. (ed) Pointing: Where Embodied Cognition meets Symbolic Mind Humana Mente, 24. Journal of Philosophical Studies | |
dc.relation | Thompson, E. 2007 Mind in life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the sciences of the mind, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. | |
dc.relation | Tomasello, M. 1995 “Joint Attention as Social Cognition”, En: Moore, Ch., & Dunham, P. J. (eds) Joint Attention: Its origins and Role in Development, Psychology Press (Taylor and Francis Group), NewYork/Sussex. (1995/2014) | |
dc.relation | Tomasello, M. 2003 The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition, Harvard U.P. London. | |
dc.relation | Tomasello, M. 2005 “Understanding and sharing intentions: The origins of cultural cognition”, Behavioral and brain scienc-es (2005) 28, 675–735 | |
dc.relation | Tomasello, M. 2009 Why we cooperate, A Boston Review Book, MIT Press, Cambridge MA. | |
dc.relation | Tomasello, M. 2012 A Natural History of Human Thinking, Harvard, U.P. London. | |
dc.relation | Tomasello, M., and Moll, M. 2007 “Cooperation and human cognition: the Vygotskian intelligence hypothesis”, Philosophical Transac-tions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, Apr 29; 362(1480): 639–648. | |
dc.relation | Torrance, S., and Froese, T. 2011 “An inter-enactive approach to agency: participatory sense-making, dynamics, and sociality”, Hu-mana Mente 15, 21–53. | |
dc.relation | Trevarthen, C. 1979 “Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of primary intersubjectivity.” En: M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before speech. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979. | |
dc.relation | Turner, Ph. 2016 HCI Redux. The promise of Post-Cognitive Interaction. Human-Computer Interaction Series. Springer, Switzerland. | |
dc.relation | Vanderschraaf, P., & Sillari, G, 2014 "Common Knowledge", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/common-knowledge/>. | |
dc.relation | Vink, R., Wijnants, M., Cillessen, A, & Bosman, A., 2017 "Cooperative Learning and Interpersonal Synchrony." Nonlinear Dynamics, Psychology, and Life Scienc-es 21, no. 2 (2017): 189-215 | |
dc.relation | Walton, A.E, Richardson, M.J, Langland-Hassan, P. y Chemero, A. 2015 “Improvisation and the self-organization of multiple musical bodies”, Frontiers in psychology, 313 (6), 1- 9. | |
dc.relation | Weinberg, M. K., & Tronick, E. Z. 1996 “Infant affective reactions to the resumption of maternal interaction after the still-face” Child Development, 67, 905-914. | |
dc.relation | Wilby, M., 2010 “The Simplicity of Mutual Knowledge”, Philosophical Explorations 13 (2):83-100 | |
dc.relation | Wilby, M., 2014 “The Sense in Joint Attention” (Draft, compartido en conversasiones personales). | |
dc.relation | Woodward, A. L. 2003 “Infants’ developing understanding of the link between looker and object”, Developmental Science, 6, 297-311. | |
dc.relation | Yu C, Smith LB 2013 “Joint Attention without Gaze Following: Human Infants and Their Parents Coordinate Visual At Tension to Objects through Eye-Hand Coordination” PLoS ONE 8(11) | |
dc.relation | Zahavi, D. 2015 “You, Me, and We: The Sharing of Emotional Experiences” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 22 (1-2), January. | |
dc.rights | Atribución-NoComercial-SinDerivadas 4.0 Internacional | |
dc.rights | Acceso abierto | |
dc.rights | http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ | |
dc.rights | info:eu-repo/semantics/openAccess | |
dc.rights | Derechos reservados - Universidad Nacional de Colombia | |
dc.title | Atención conjunta mediada: un ensayo sobre el entendimiento involucrado en la cooperación dependiente de la percepción | |
dc.type | Otro | |