dc.creatorElders, Leo J.
dc.date.accessioned2021-10-27T11:52:47Z
dc.date.accessioned2022-09-29T16:39:09Z
dc.date.available2021-10-27T11:52:47Z
dc.date.available2022-09-29T16:39:09Z
dc.date.created2021-10-27T11:52:47Z
dc.date.issued2003
dc.identifierElders, L. J. The Transcendental properties of being [en línea]. Sapientia. 2003, 57 (212). Disponible en: https://repositorio.uca.edu.ar/handle/123456789/12577
dc.identifier0036-4703
dc.identifierhttps://repositorio.uca.edu.ar/handle/123456789/12577
dc.identifier.urihttp://repositorioslatinoamericanos.uchile.cl/handle/2250/3792959
dc.description.abstractIn metaphysics the term «transcendental» is used to denote the different aspects of being, that is of whatever is real. The term indicates that being and its properties are present in each of the predicaments or categories, such as substance, quantity, quality, relation, location, time, action, etc. Therefore, they «transcend» the limits of these different classesl. Some early Greek philosophers had noticed that whatever exists must have some unity and goodness, but they never treated the theme systematically. The philosophy of being begins with Parmenides who describes his fulgurant intuition of the unitary and unchangeable character of being as having been revealed to him from aboye. Being is and not-being is not. Being is one and immutable; it is also knowable, for being and thinking, he writes, are the same. A century later Plato intimates that the highest reality, the Good, is beautiful and is one. However, he did not say that all existent things are good and beautiful...
dc.languageeng
dc.publisherPontificia Universidad Católica Argentina. Facultad de Filosofía y Letras
dc.rightshttp://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/
dc.rightsAcceso abierto
dc.sourceSapientia Vol. 57, No. 212, 2003
dc.subjectSER
dc.subjectONTOLOGIA
dc.subjectMETAFISICA
dc.titleThe Transcendental properties of being
dc.typeArtículos de revistas


Este ítem pertenece a la siguiente institución